The Unsatisfactory Mystery of Divine Action

June 9th, 2013 / 10 Comments

I just finished a wonderfully accessible and clear book on God’s activity in the world. It was written from an advocate of Thomas Aquinas’s theology, and it addresses recent scientific theory and scholarship. I’ll be recommending that serious scholars of science and theology read this book…

even though I strongly disagree with its proposals!

I know of no finer, more accurate, or more accessible explanation of a Thomistic view of divine action than Michael Dodds’s recently published book, Unlocking Divine Action: Contemporary Science and Thomas Aquinas. This is an immensely important book, and those who care about issues of divine action would do well to read it.

But this book only deepened my belief that the Thomistic approach to divine causation is unsatisfactory. We need alternatives.

Causal Categories

Dodds begins by rightly arguing that divine causation – the notion that God acts as a causal force in the world — is a central concern for our time. Contemporary philosophy of science, however, has reduced the number of causal categories to just one: the category of efficient causes. We think today about causation in terms of the impact of one entity upon another.

Dodds uses Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas to argue for additional categories of causation. Early chapters in the book explain accessibly Aristotle’s four causes: material, formal, efficient, and final. Aquinas employed these four causes for his own theological work, believing them to give a full account of causality. We should use these four causes, says Dodds, to talk about causation amongst creatures and God’s own causal activity.

The major contribution Thomas Aquinas makes to Aristotle’s scheme, however, is to argue that a result or outcome in the world can come through both a primary cause – associated with God – and a secondary cause – associated with creatures.

Because only efficient causality has remained in the contemporary scientific world, says Dodds, “the very success that science enjoyed by omitting causes that could not be measured eventually led to the conviction that such causes should not only be ignored methodologically but denied metaphysically” (50). This denial of additional causes led to philosophical reductionism: the basic parts of the world, which apparently persist via efficient causation, are the most real. Efficient causation consequently led to many scholars framing causality in terms of mechanism. The result of a mechanistic world led to scientism, says Dodds, which is the view that only science can give us truth about the world.

Causality and Recent Science

In recent years, however, change has been taking place in philosophy of science.  The theory of emergence now plays an important explanatory role, for instance. Emergence says that we should think of the natural world as comprised of multiple levels, and new features can arise at one level. These features cannot be explained simply by their parts or by what occurs at less complex levels.

In addition, quantum mechanics suggests indeterminacy exists at the least complex levels of existence. This indeterminacy means not only that variance occurs at these levels of existence, but that we cannot be entirely certain about our observations. Dodds notes that evolutionary theory is becoming more influenced by notions of purpose and direction. This development places into question the rigid mechanism assumed by some philosophies of science.

Perhaps most important to Dodds’s project is his claim that many now seek causal explanations that go beyond efficient causation. According to Dodds, science itself now cries out for causal explanations beyond efficient causality alone.

The reduction of causality to one category – efficient causation – led to the reduction of our ability to speak about God’s causal activity. Put simply: the scientific worldview seemed to allow no room for God to act. Many engaging science-and-religion scholarship today are searching for a theoretical and empirical space — “a causal joint” — at which God may work in the world. Dodd regards this search as the quest for a univocal cause, in which God actions are similar in kind to creaturely actions but do not interfere the laws of nature or creaturely causality.

Many theologians in the modern period, says Dodds, responded to science by accepting the philosophical limitation that causation comes only through efficient causes. Here, process theology and theologies espousing divine self-limitation come under Dodds’s scrutiny. Unfortunately, however, this section is one of the weakest in the book. The author misrepresents what the majority of process theologians have said (and the footnotes reveal a lack of research in this area).

Perhaps more unfortunate, Dodds never addresses in this section the crucial question driving much of modern theology: Does or can God completely control others (act as sufficient cause)? This question not only drives quests to solve the problem of evil, it also plays an important role in philosophy of science questions about causal explanations.

A major segment of Unlocking Divine Action addresses new theories of contemporary science and how those engaging in science-and-theology research use these theories to speculate about how God acts in the world.  For instance, Dodds looks at how some scholars speculate that God might input information into the natural world to exert causal influence. He looks at the possibilities open to the science-and-religion scholars by the apparent phenomenon of quantum indeterminacy. Dodds explores the possibility of God’s influencing the emergence of new structures in the natural world. All of the proposals Dodds explores suggest non-interventionist types of divine action: God exerts causal influence without circumventing creaturely influence.

God is Not Like Us (in ANY way!)

Dodds is not convinced, however, by recent science-and-religion proposals on non-interventionist divine action. His primary criticism is that most science-and-religion scholars think God’s activity is of the same general kind as creaturely activity. In other words, these theories presuppose a univocal understanding of divine and creaturely causality.

Those who presuppose a theory of causality based on univocity, argues Dodds, inevitably wrestle with the question of God’s interference. “When divine action is conceived univocally with the action of creatures, divine being tends to be viewed univocally as well. A univocal God, however, is quite different than the God of the Christian tradition” (158).

Not only does Dodd think God’s being is altogether different from creaturely being, but he thinking of them as of the same metaphysical kind leads to worrying that God and creatures compete as causes. “When two men carry a table,” Dodds says by way of illustration, “the more weight one lifts, the less there is for the other to lift” (153). But “God is unlike all other things,” he Dodds. “Recognizing this, we should be cautious about trying to say anything about how God acts. God is totally other” (161). For this reason, Dodds says, “the mode or manner of divine activity will ever escape us” (169).

The alternative Dodds presents is a return to the past: the proposals of Thomas Aquinas. According to Aquinas, there are no real relations or mutual dependency between God and creation.  Creatures depend upon God and are related to God. But God has no corresponding relation to creatures, and God is not dependent in any way.

With Aquinas, Dodds believes that “God’s action is fundamentally different from that of creatures” (171). “To predicate such a relation of God,” says Dodds, “would be to reduce God to the level of one creature existing beside another” (172). Instead, it is impossible to speak of divine action in any positive way: “our verbal and conceptual abilities should be utterly defeated if we try to speak of God, since God is utterly beyond the being of creatures” (174).

Primary and Secondary Causation

But if it’s impossible for us to speak of God, where does this leave the one who seeks to talk about God’s action in relation to science?

Dodds believes the primary/secondary theory of causation offers the best way to talk about divine action and creaturely causation. According to this view, every instance of creaturely causality necessarily requires God’s influence. But God acts as a primary cause and does not conflict with the secondary causes. After all, argues Dodds, “these causes do not belong to the same order” (191). God’s causality infinitely transcends creaturely causality. And this means that “when a primary and secondary cause act together, the effect belongs entirely to both. The influence of the primary cause does not diminish the action of the secondary cause, but enables it” (192).

It’s important for Dodds, however, to insist that “the use of secondary causes does not despeak any divine limitation” (192). In fact, “God’s causality does not constitute a miraculous intervention; nor does it negate the real causality of all the natural agents involved in the evolutionary process” (202). Whenever an event occurs in the world, we can say both that God caused it and that creatures caused it.

Dodds admits that this proposal borders on incomprehensibility: “the notion of secondary causation is not an easy one to grasp” (207). But he agrees with Etienne Gilson that “we must hold firmly to two apparently contradictory truths. God does whatever creatures do; and that creatures themselves do whatever they do” (208). This double agency of the primary/secondary theory is a paradox. Both God and creatures can be the causes of what occurs in reality, because as the primary cause, God transcends all categories of creaturely causation.

The Mystery Card

This is where my dissatisfaction for the Dodds/Thomas Aquinas proposal comes out strongly. In essence, Dodds is proposing what Ian Barbour called the “independence” model for thinking about science and theology: science and theology are independent explanations, and the two have no overlapping commonalities. God’s action is independent from creaturely actions, and God’s action is in no way analogous to creaturely action. In fact, we cannot say anything positive about God’s causal activity or God’s being, because God is utterly beyond our language and categories of being.

In the end, then, it’s all about mystery for Dodds. It’s mystery in the unsatisfactory sense of our not even being able to offer any meaningful explanation for God’s causal activity in relation to creaturely causation.

The primary/secondary theory of Dodds and Thomas Aquinas strikes me as an elaborate mystery card played to retain a role for both divine and creaturely causation – theology and science – without having to make difficult decisions about ancient questions – e.g., why does a loving and powerful God not prevent evil? – or contemporary scientific issues – e.g., how does God act as an efficient cause?

And as the book winds down, Dodds explores what his primary/secondary theme entails for providence, miracles, and theodicy. He quickly appeals to mystery when confronted with the problem of evil: It is a problem “no theology can answer or ‘solve’” (240). Dodds is not willing to entertain any notion of divine limitations, because he believes such limitations result in even greater theological difficulties.

Dodds ultimately offers the unsatisfactory proposal that God allows evil without directly intending it. He explores prayer and miracles near the end of the book as well, using the primary/secondary scheme. Important questions about God’s ability to act as a sufficient cause to answer prayer or act miraculously are not addressed to this reviewer’s satisfaction. But this is expected after the previous and longer section on evil and Dodds’s repeated appeals to mystery.

The Causality of Love?

Dodds concludes the book with a short section he titles, “The Causality of Love.” As one who has published a great deal on the metaphysics of love, I was especially keen to see what he would write in this very brief segment. Dodds believes his primary/secondary approach allows us to say God acts lovingly and creatures can partner with God. But after reading earlier in the book that God’s causality and being are altogether different from creaturely causality and being,

I wondered how words like “partnership” or “cooperation” or even “participation” make any sense when used in relation to God and creation. And what does “love” even mean when our language about God, according to Dodds, offers nothing positive about God’s being or relations. In short, the appeal to love fell flat.

Despite my strong criticism of Unlocking Divine Action, I think this is an important book. I will be recommending it often. To my mind, it illustrates why many today are seeking ways to talk about divine action other than what we find in Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, Michael Dodds, and those who think similarly.

Sometimes I need a lucid book and carefully argued thesis to see clearly the need for something better.

Add comment

Comments

Charles W. Christian

Honest question (I, too, find Thomistic “solutions” unsatisfactory overall, but I don’t always see your conclusions (or Process conclusions in general) as doing the trick either): SO, is there a sense in which you see God’s approach as distinctly different from that of humans?  In other words, is there a transcendent aspect to God’s workings in love that you would be comfortable labeling as either “mysterious” or “other” from the realm of logic or nature?  What might that look like?  Thanks…. I hope my question makes sense….Blessings!


Ben Duarte

Dr. Oord, Thank you for your critique of “Unlocking Divine Action”, it seems like an interesting read. A couple of ideas came to mind at the end of the assessment.
You felt that Dodds offered a return to the past? You said: “The alternative Dodds presents is a return to the past: the proposals of Thomas Aquinas. According to Aquinas, there are no real relations or mutual dependency between God and creation.  Creatures depend upon God and are related to God. But God has no corresponding relation to creatures, and God is not dependent in any way”.
In this, one thought/question that came to mind was the sacraments of the Roman Catholic Church. Wasn’t it a basic belief of Thomas Aquinas that human beings enjoyed a relation to God through communion? Also, Would you comment on Thomas Aquinas’ words: “Some truths about God exceed all the ability of human reason. But there are some truths which natural reason also is able to reach” (On the truth of the Catholic faith, Thomas Aquinas).
Here was my second thought, you said: “Dodds believes his primary/secondary approach allows us to say God acts lovingly and creatures can partner with God. But after reading earlier in the book that God’s causality and being are altogether different from creaturely causality and being, I wondered how words like “partnership” or “cooperation” or even “participation” make any sense when used in relation to God and creation. And what does “love” even mean when our language about God, according to Dodds, offers nothing positive about God’s being or relations. In short, the appeal to love fell flat.”
In this, there seems to be a presupposition that ‘partnership’, ‘cooperation’, ‘participation’ and essentially ‘love’ cannot genuinely occur between humans and God unless God and humans correspond (have a close similarity)- How ‘similar’ do humans need to be to God for partnership or love to be a possibility?
Please comment at your interest and convenience- Thank you!


Jeannine Howard

Ben—great comment, you “efficiently” expressed the “cause” of my inquiries. smile Humanity has always wanted succinct answers to what are most likely unanswerable questions,but makes for great reading.  Thanks for the article Tom—-Aquinas vs. Oord!


Ben Duarte

Jeannine, thank you for your kind words. I too, enjoy reading articles by Dr. Oord. And, interacting with others here.


Thomas Jay Oord

Charles,

Yes, I affirm divine transcendence. But I don’t think we should think of transcendence as either utter mystery or God’s spatial distance from creation. Rather, I think transcendence refers to how God differs from creatures. And I think God (and God’s love) differs from creatures in many ways. For instance, God exists necessarily, everlastingly, and is everywhere. Creatures are contingent, not everlasting, and localized. I could cite many other differences, but I think you get my point.

Thanks!

Tom


Thomas Jay Oord

Ben,

Thanks for your posts. According to Aquinas, God has only one-directional and rational relations with creatures. I believe love requires bi-directional and affective (and rational) relations, where by the lover and beloved are mutually influencing. To put it simply: Aquinas’ God is not the God of give-and-receive relations I find often described in scripture.

As to the “similarity” between creatures and God, see my response to Charles above. I will add, however, that I think love itself as expressed by God and creatures is the same in kind. In other words, I think divine love and creaturely love involves acting intentionally, in response to others, to promote overall well-being.

Tom


Thomas Jay Oord

Thanks for the comment, Jeanine. I hope my response to Ben helps. And thanks for the compliment!

Tom


Ben Duarte

Dr. Oord,
Thank you for taking time to reply. Theology is truly enjoyable. 
“According to Aquinas, God has only one-directional and rational relations with creatures. I believe love requires bi-directional and affective (and rational) relations, where by the lover and beloved are mutually influencing. To put it simply: Aquinas’ God is not the God of give-and-receive relations I find often described in scripture.”
First thought,
I would like to reply by saying that I agree that God has ‘rational’ relations with creatures. I also appreciate the reasoning from scripture, although, that is not always the only motif (I assume you agree). I would like to ask, If the God of Aquinas relates to humans by the rational, does this mean that ‘love’ is not possible? Or in authentic existence? For example, suppose God loves one creature that happens to reside in New York City at this very moment. But this creature does not believe, nor love God in return; of course in this capacity I would be uncertain of the creature’s ‘influence’ on God, but nonetheless, does God’s love for this New York City creature not exist in our ontology? (including history?)I would agree that love should be ‘give and receive’- but did God exhibit his love for all on the cross? (the giving of God) while with creatures, when they ‘believe’ can give back to God? Unless, we can show that there must be at least two persons both loving each other, for love to ‘come into existence’. On the other hand, ‘God is love’- God is also three persons, which love each other.
I take your point. I can also see the same as far as scripture ‘describing God as give-and receive-, I can also see there are times when God gives, and creatures do not. I am not confident that this excludes love from existence.
Second thought,
Is your intrinsic point that even if Aquinas wanted to ‘give’ (love)to God, he could not since his view of God does not allow it?
Your last point, I would agree with strongly, that love is ‘intentional’.


Chris Donato

Just wondering out loud here: doesn’t Aquinas present (or build up to) the Christ event at the exact point that he affirms the altogether unlikeness of God’s causality and being and man’s? Is this not part and parcel of Aquinas’ Western spin on Eastern thought re: man the microcosmic creator, the incarnation as a cosmic event, and deification? And thus the disparity in relations is resolved?


Steven Heintz

Surprisingly a good and satisfying read on this subject is found in On the Bondage of the Will by Martin Luther. J. I. Packer’s translation is excellent – with a good Introduction.


Leave a Comment

Your email address will not be published.

You may use these HTML tags and attributes: <a href="" title=""> <abbr title=""> <acronym title=""> <b> <blockquote cite=""> <cite> <code> <del datetime=""> <em> <i> <q cite=""> <s> <strike> <strong>

Type in all 5 of the digits below to leave a comment. * Time limit is exhausted. Please reload CAPTCHA.